The Most Certain Principle

Cresswell calls this the Most Certain Principle:

MCP: if we have two sentences A and B, and A is true and B is false, then A and B do not mean the same.

Last year, I thought that this principle was most certainly false: if I say something true that is false at another world w, and somebody in w says something with the same content, then our utterances mean the same while they differ in truth value. To quote myself,

Consider a possible world that differs from ours only by containing an extra isolated electron in some remote part of the universe, far outside our galaxy. When I say "the number of electrons is even", my utterance differs in truth value from the corresponding utterance of my twin at this world. Does it follow that we mean different things by "number" or "electron" or "even" (or "is")?

I still believe the Most Certain Principle is false, but I no longer think this is a good reason. Cresswell could respond that our two utterances of "the number of electrons is even" really do mean different things: I make a claim about my world, my twin makes a claim about his world. After all, if (per impossibile) a trusting hearer were to hear both utterances, they would learn different things -- as we do when we simultaneously hear two people in different rooms say "it's cold in here". If my twin wanted to say something that has the same meaning as my sentence, he would have to say something like "in alpha, the number of electrons is even", where "alpha" denotes my world.

Contents, on this view, have their truth value eternally and essentially. The content expressed by "it's raining" in the present context is not just that it's raining on May 08 at 23:25 in Canberra, but that it's raining on May 08 at 23:25 in Canberra in world alpha. This is true everywhere, at every time, at every world. Such contents therefore can't be modeled as divisions of possibilities: what is expressed is either true at all worlds or false at all worlds.

This, I thought, is silly: obviously we can express and believe contingent things. But an advocate of MCP could reply that there are two ways of evaluating thoughts or contents at a world. On the first way, we evaluate a tokening of the very same thought or content located at the other world. For instance, we consider an utterance with the exact same content there and figure out its truth value. On this way, we always get the same truth value, because sameness of content entails sameness of truth value. But on the second way, we abstract from the content a certain condition for the actual world and then determine whether that condition is satisfied at other worlds. The condition abstracted from the content that it's raining on May 08 at 23:25 in Canberra in world alpha is the condition satisfied at a world w iff it's raining on May 08 at 23:25 in Canberra in w. If a content is contingent, then that's because it is false at some worlds according to the second way.

The second way of evaluating contents at worlds effects a division among possibilities, a function from possible worlds to truth values. But this function is not the meaning or content itself, nor is the actual content a Russellian proposition of an ordinary kind. Something at another world can make the very same division of possibilities, and express the same Russellian proposition, but have a different truth value. By MCP, therefore, these candidates are not the meaning.

Thus it is a little puzzling that many outspoken advocates of MCP, including Cresswell and Stalnaker, are also outspoken advocates of modeling content by divisions among possibilities. Maybe they don't really endorse MCP. Most philosophers simply ignore the trans-world application of MCP and pretend that if contents don't change their truth-value within a world, then MCP will be satisfied. This indicates that they might have a weaker version in mind:

MCP2: if we have two sentences A and B, and A is true and B is false within the same world, then A and B do not mean the same.

I would recommend going further:

MCP3: if we have two sentences A and B, and A is true and B is false in the same context, then A and B do not mean the same.

I would even strengthen this to a biconditional: A and B have the same meaning iff they have the same truth value in all contexts. People often object to this on the ground that meanings are the ultimate bearers of truth values. I don't quite see how that argument goes: why can't meanings bear a truth value without essentially and eternally bearing it, like St. Petersburg bears the name "St. Petersburg" today, but didn't bear it in 1937? But anyway, if that argument is any good, it works just as well against a notion of meaning based on MCP2.

If MCP was as obviously false as I thought last year, that would be a good reason to suppose that everyone who claims to endorse it actually only endorses something like MCP2. But now that I no longer think it obviously false, I wonder if maybe some really accept MCP. Here is a curious passage from Stalnaker's Inquiry that looks like he does.

Take Mabel, for example, who has arthritis and also has many beliefs about arthritis. One of them is that she has recently developed arthritis in her thigh [...]. Now compare the actual situation with the counterfactual situation where Mabel's inner states and dispositions are just as they actually are [...]. What is different in the counterfactual situation is the way certain words are used, not by Mabel but by other people. The word "arthritis", in this counterfactual situation, is properly used to refer to a wider class of rheumatoid ailments, including the one that is afflicting Mabel's thigh. [...] [T]he belief that she would express there by saying "I have arthritis in my thigh" is a true belief. It follows that Mabel's belief in the actual world is different from her belief in the counterfactual world [...]. (Inquiry, p.67, my emphasis)

By what principle does this conclusion follow? The only candidate I can see is the MCP: Mabel's belief in the counterfactual situation is true, her belief in the actual situation is false, therefore different content. By this reasoning, just about any contingent belief Mabel has in the counterfactual world will have a different content from her corresponding actual belief (and this has nothing to do with linguistic division of labour).

Comments

# on 10 May 2007, 09:35

Hi Wolfgang,

my spontaneous thought upon reading the last bits of your entry is that you omit information that Stalnakers relies on in his inference. What assumptions does he have in mind, when he writes “It follows”?

Let S be the sentence "I have Arthritis in my thigh" and let w be a counterfactual situation as described.

You seem to suggest, he draws his conclusion merely from

(1) The belief that Mabel de facto expresses with S is false.
(2) The belief that Mabel expresses with S in w is true.

But, if I remember the story correctly, there is more other important information; first of all, information about some non-semantic state of affairs (those states that Mabel's actual belief is about):

(3) De facto, Mabel has some kind of rheumatoid ailment, not Arthritis in her thigh.
(4) In w, Mabel has some kind of rheumatoid ailment, not Arthritis in her thigh.

Secondly, semantic information about the parts of S:

(5) The reference of „Arthtritis“ in w differs from its actual reference.
(6) The other words of S function in w just like they function de facto.

Stalnaker draws a conclusion from the story he told us, and the story provides us with much information: relevant are (1) to (6). To conclude from (1) to (6) the way Stalnaker does, does not presuppose MCP.

What do you think?

Best,

Benjamin.

# on 10 May 2007, 17:47

Moin moin Benjamin,

I agree that it isn't obvious Stalnaker uses MCP here. Though he says "it follows" right after stating that what Mabel expresses by "I have arthritis..." is true in w. So the reasoning presumably has something to do with this sentence being true in w.

(3), (4) and (6) state similarities between @ and w, so can hardly be reasons for drawing conclusions about a difference in content. That this leaves (5): the reference of "arthritis" differs. It is unclear to me how it would follow from this that the belief Mabel expresses by using the word has a different content, but you're right that this is a possibility.

# on 11 May 2007, 08:53

Hi wo,

Stalnaker's conclusion is that the belief first mentioned in the story is not identical to the belief later mentioned. You apparently say you find it hard to see how to derive this result from the story, if not by employing MCP (actually, you say something different, because you talk about the beliefs having different contents, but in the quotation we seem to have non-identity of belief).

Here is a suggestion on how to get the result, without MCP, from the story. I will rely on the following schematic principle:

TB (Truth for Belief):
If B is the belief that P, then B is true iff P.

We have the following information from the story:

(1) B is the belief that Mabel has Arthritis in her thigh.
(2) in w: Mabel has Arthritis in her thigh.
(3) in w: B* is false

We can reason thus:

(C) B is true in w [from (1), (2), TB]
(C.1) B and B* have different properties in w. [(1), (3)]
(C.2) B and B* are not identical in w. [Leibniz’s Law]
(C.3) B and B* are not identical. [Necessity of =]

This kind of reasoning seems to me to deliver the goods, and - as far as I see right now - it does not employ MCP.

Benjamin.

# on 12 May 2007, 16:20

I always wondered what systematic use is made of the MCP: Is it suppose to help us to understand something about meaning, it does look far too general to be of any real use.
And I always thought that surely nobody is taking MCP as being really about sentences (without context), otherwise every statement with indexicals would be a counterexample, so it must be something like MCP3 that is really meant. So it should be stated as being about utterances, can we workout something like MCP3 that would hold for sentences (take to be utterace types across contexts)?

M.

# on 13 May 2007, 05:34

Thanks Benjamin. Your suggestion resembles the following argument that I'm sure I've seen a few times:

1. In @, Mabel believes that she has arthritis in her thigh.
2. It is impossible to have arthritis in one's thigh.
3. What Mabel believes in w is true.
4. Therefore, what Mabel believes in w is not that she has arthritis in her thigh.
5. Therefore, her beliefs in @ and w are different.

Your suggestion seems different, however: you say it's actually possible to have arthritis in one's thigh (your 2); and that Mabel does believe in w that she has arthritis in her thigh (your 1, assuming B is the belief in w). Then her belief in w is true in w (your C, vindicating Stalnaker's claim), while her belief in @ is not true in w (your 3). Right? I'm not quite sure how to get your (3) on the assumption that Mabel has arthritis in her thigh in w: doesn't she actually believe she has arthritis in her thigh?

M: you're right that one needs to say something about contexts in MCP. But the form in which most people interpret and use it is not MCP3, but:

MCP') if a sentence A is true in some context, and a sentence B is false in some context, then A and B do not mean the same.

The crucial difference is that the contexts are allowed to be different. Take the Lycan quote from the older post: "of an Earth utterance and its Twin, one may be true and the other false; what more could be required for difference of meaning?" That is an application of MCP', not of MCP3. Since the utterances plainly take place in different contexts, MCP3 does not licence an inference to a difference in content.

# on 13 May 2007, 19:49

Oh, oh,

I guess I mixed up "true" and "false"; I often do that.

Seriously, (2) and (3) were of course meant to be the other way round:

(2) in w: It is not the case that Mabel has Arthritis in her thigh.
(3) in w: B* is true

Then we have it that in w, B is false and B* is true and everything continues as before. Sorry for the confusion.

Then, the argument can proceed as above and without MCP.

Ben

Add a comment

Please leave these fields blank (spam trap):

No HTML please.
You can edit this comment until 30 minutes after posting.