Quiddistic Knowledge, Quiddistic Belief

In their contributions to Lewisian Themes, Rae Langton and Jonathan Schaffer both argue that quidditism -- the claim that possible worlds may differ only in which intrinsic properties play which causal/nomological roles -- does not entail skepticism about intrinsic natures because standard replies to skepticism about the external world carry over to skepticism about intrinsic natures.

But it seems to me that there is an important difference: if quidditism is true, we not only lack knowledge about intrinsic natures, but also any beliefs about them.

I believe that there are neurons in the primate visual cortex that selectively respond to horizontal lines in the visual field; skeptics argue that this belief is unjustified, that I don't really know that these neurons exist. Suppose they are wrong. But consider Fred who has no opinion whatsoever about neurons in the primate visual cortex. It would be very odd to claim that despite that he, too, knows that there are neurons in the primate visual cortex that selectively respond to horizontal lines in the visual field. If quidditism is true, then I believe that with respect to intrinsic natures we are in the situation Fred is with respect to neurons in the visual cortex.

Let w1 be a world where fundamental property F plays the mass role and w2 a world where some other (alien) property G plays that role. Do my beliefs distinguish between w1 and w2? I don't think so.

First, no possible evidence could distinguish between w1 and w2; so if my credences in these possibilities differ, they would have to differ because one of them had higher prior credence than the other. But how could the F-world appear more likely than the G-world? The case is very unlike that of counter-inductive worlds or vat worlds: rationality demands assigning low credence to those, as does leading an ordinary life. But it is hard to see how it could be rational to believe in the F-possibility rather than the G-possibility, and how that could matter for everyday life. In fact, this seems to be a safe case for applying indifference: it would be irrational, one might argue, to assign anything but the same credence to the F- and the G-world. (Things are different for worlds where properties have only partly traded places.)

Second, nothing about my behaviour indicates that I believe in the one possibility rather than the other. If some remote part of this world contained a twin earth where F and G have traded places, I wouldn't notice if, overnight, I were swapped with my twin on that planet. Nor are my states and those of my twin differently responsive to F- and G-perceptions: any external circumstances apt to cause a certain belief in my twin is equally apt to cause the corresponding belief in me.

Third, it is important not to get confused by belief ascriptions. I believe that some things have mass. If "mass" rigidly denotes whatever occupies the mass role, say F, then "some things have mass" is true at exactly those worlds where some things have F. So, one might conclude, what I believe rules out the G world. But that's an unhelpful way of describing things: by this reasoning, anyone who believes that the actual Prime Minister of Liechtenstein rules a small country believes that Otmar Hasler rules a small country. What's true is that I identify mass by its role; the belief I express by saying that some things have mass is that some things have whatever occupies the mass role. That's true in both the F and the G world.

So I think the usual moves against skepticism can't rescue quiddistic knowledge because we don't even have quidditic belief.

Comments

# on 16 August 2006, 16:35

Hey wo,

Just an initial thought after reading your post, which I agree might raise something in the neighborhood of a potential difficulty for Schaffer and Langton. The beginning of your post read as if you planned to raise challenges regarding how one could acquire and form a belief about *any* quiddity, i.e. how quiddistic beliefs are possible. (At least, that's the only way in which the Fred case seems relevant in your discussion.) But the three specific challenges you raise are regarding how one could acquire and form a belief about *one quiddity as opposed to another*. So even if the three specific challenges are successful, they are not challenges to the possibility of quiddistic belief in general, but to how finely grained it could be. So my initial thought is whether we should conflate these two (obviously tightly related but not equivalent) sorts of challenges to quiddistic belief. For all you've shown, it may be the case that coarsely grained quiddistic beliefs are all that's necessary for quiddistic knowledge.

# on 17 August 2006, 00:27

I just wanted to endorse the general line of thought you sketch here. One reason I think this is an important point to make is that it parallels a similar confusion concerning Kant. It's still common to understand Kant to be claiming that we cannot *know* things as they are in themselves. But while this is true, it isn't the fundamental claim Kant is interested in when he discusses these issues. Rather Kant's basic claim is that we can't form certain sorts of representations about things-in-themselves. Or, roughly, that we can't form certain sorts of beliefs about them. (Any claims about knowledge follow from these more basic claims.)

Here again, as your comments suggest, the sorts of representations Kant is interested in are representations that allow us to distinguish different things from one another (that allow us "compare them with respect to identity and diversity"). So, in fact, I think Kant's basic conception of these issues (and his most basic arguments for this conception) are much closer to Lewis than might at first appear to be the case. (Although Kant's arguments, as I understand them, don't *require* quidditism - so if you think Lewis' arguments do (which I'm not sure about), then Kant may be one up on Lewis here.)

# on 17 August 2006, 22:58

Thanks Karl. Just on your last note: I think at least Lewis wasn't really interested in making a strong case for humility. What he cared about is combinatorialism, and that (as it were) just happened to entail quidditism and humility. (Lewis also mentions the 'replacement argument' that only requires a somewhat weaker form of quidditism, but I don't think it makes a big difference.)

Alex, I'm not sure I understand your point. By a quiddistic belief I mean a belief whose content cuts across possibilities that differ quiddistically, that is, a belief whose content contains some possibility w1 but not some possibility w2 even though w1 and w2 differ only in that two fundamental properties have traded places. If quidditism is true and this kind of swapping is possible for a property, then I don't think one can have a belief *about that property* in the relevant sense that is not quidditistic. So I think those "two" kinds of quiddistic beliefs coincide. Does that make sense?

Add a comment

Please leave these fields blank (spam trap):

No HTML please.
You can edit this comment until 30 minutes after posting.