I'm trying to finish my thesis before February 1st. So this David Lewis blog might eventually become a more general philosophy blog again soon. For the remainder of this month, I probably won't be blogging very much.
By the way, I made a fool of myself by asking physicists about whether elementary particles are extended. As expected, the answer is that the question doesn't make sense in quantum mechanics.
Shelby Moore: "The specification (by definition of specification) does not
allow deviations which would violate the specification."
What, in general, does it mean that something A satisfies a predicate 'F'?
Traditionally, there are three candidates:
1) 'A is F' means that A is F. That' all. Simple predications can't be analysed.
2) 'A is F' means that A instantiates the property F. Except in some special cases,
in particular the case where 'F' is 'instantiates'.
3) 'A is F' always means that A instantiates the property F.
It is not entirely obvious how to locate Lewis here. In some places, when
discussing Armstrong's request for analyses (or truthmakers) for
predication, he sounds like he favours (1): "the statement that A has F
is true because A has F. It's so because it's so. It just is." ("A world
of truthmakers", p.219 in Papers)
Brian Weatherson tells me that Lewis does mention Goodman's 'New Riddle' as
a task for natural properties in "Meaning without use: Reply to Hawthorne".
Lewis says here that we should not be scared off by "Kripkenstein's
challenge (formerly Goodman's challenge)" to find a distinction between
natural and unnatural extrapolation (p.150 in Papers in Ethics and
Social Philosophy, similar remarks can be found in the introduction to
Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology). So the first suggestion
is very probably right.
(Reading Brian's comments it now seems to me when I argued that natural
properties can't solve the New Riddle I've been confusing it with the Old
Riddle. All the New Riddle requires is an objective distinction between
good and bad extrapolations. That induction based on good extrapolations
might nevertheless yield systematically false predictions ("not work") is the
Old Riddle.)
I think these conditions match the dot-matrix test better than the ones I
proposed earlier. They are more complicated, but closer to the matrices
and not too unnatural:
A property F is natural to the extent that the following conditions are
satisfied, where (1), (3) and (5) weigh heavier than (2), (4) and (6).
1) The Fs resemble each other intrinsically.
2) The Fs resemble each other extrinsically.
3) Anything that exactly resembles an F intrinsically is itself F.
4) Anything that exactly resembles an F extrinsically is itself F.
5) There are few intrinsic F-gaps.
6) There are few extrinsic F-gaps.
Something y is an intrinsic (extrinsic) F-gap if it isn't F and there are
Fs x and z such that y intrinsically (extrinsically) resembles both of them
more closely than x intrinsically (extrinsically) resembles z.
RL satisfies all conditions except (3), whereas R only properly satisfies
(1).
In section 6 of "Redefining 'Intrinsic'" (Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research 62, 2001), Lewis introduces an interesting test for comparative
naturalness of properties. The test is based on two-dimensional dot-matrix
pictures, where distance along the horizontal dimension measures intrinsic
dissimilarity, and distance along the vertical dimension extrinsic
dissimilarity. Roughly (p.385), a natural property demarcates a regular
region in the dot-matrix. Less roughly (p.391), two aspects of the region
are important for naturalness: spread and scatter.
Brian Weatherson has set up a weblog to track changes of online papers in philosophy, similar to my diffbot, but of course much more useful for other people.
It would actually be easy to create an even more useful tracking system, which would not only update itself automatically but also provide a flexible interface so that you could, for example, list all changes to Richard Heck's papers in the last 5 months. A possibility to search for papers on a specific topic would also be helpful. Maybe I'll think about setting up such a system when Brian gets bored with his manual updates.
My logfiles indicate that people are more interested in silly
logic puzzles than in pointless remarks on footnotes in the
metaphysical writings of David Lewis. Let's see if I can get my readership
down to zero with this one.
Besides perfectly natural properties, Lewis also needs somewhat less
natural properties in his philosophy of language and elsewhere. What
determines how natural a property is? Lewis gives three different
answers, in four different places, none of them longer than two sentences.
Sometime before christmas, Greg Restall spotted a bug in my tree prover and noticed that it didn't work with Internet Explorer on MacOS X. These problems should now be fixed. I've also started working on an implementation of proofs with identity and function symbols, but I'm not sure if I'll ever finish it.
I actually wrote the tree prover to check the results of another script, which is what I vaguely talk about in the Feedback section. This is what that other script would calculate if I'd ever get it done:
David Lewis offers a lot of work for natural properties in his semantics,
his theory of mental content, materialism, supervenience, causation, laws
of nature, etc. Strikingly missing in this list (as opposed to the list of
Anthony Quinton, "Properties and Classes") is the solution of Goodman's New
Riddle of Induction. I don't know why Lewis never mentions this. Two
suggestions:
1) He thought it was just too obvious, and he disliked repeating arguments
of other philosophers (none of the items on Quinton's list occurs on
Lewis').