< 79 older entriesHome702 newer entries >

The Farrington Cases

Another nice problem from Brian Weatherson's weblog: Farrington is 50% confident that it's after 4:30, and 50% confident that a certain coin landed tails. Now he comes to know that iff the coin landed tails, some researchers create a brain-in-a-vat duplicate of himself at exactly 4:30 today. What are the probabilities he should assign to the 5 open possibilities:

The Problem of Conjunctive Events

This appears to be a problem for Lewis' theories of causation:

Let A,B,C,D be any events such that B depends counterfactually on A, and D on C. Now consider the conjunction (fusion) B+C of B and C. If A had not occurred, B+C would not have occurred. For then B would not have occurred, and presumably B+C can't happen without B. And if B+C had not occurred, C would not have occured either, so (unless the absence of B has some surprising effects on D), D would not have occurred. Hence there is a chain of counterfactual dependence between A and D. But since A,B,C,D were arbitrary, this means that every cause causes every effect.

What Montague Pointed Out

Today I found Montague's paper, and it turns out that I was wrong. Well, Field's presentation was not entirely correct: We shouldn't take Robinson arithmetic itself as R, but some extension of it that contains an additional primitive predicate "True" (T, for short). The extension need not say anything about this predicate. This is why T needn't represent truth in R. (If R says nothing about T, T either represents nothing at all or the inconsistent property, depending on how precisely we define representation.) Montague then shows, very much like Field, that any theory that contains R -- no matter if it's axiomatizable or not --, as well as every instance of

Truth, Field, Montague, and Robinson Arithmetic

So I've started to actually read Field's papers. Unfortunately I already got stuck on page 4 of "The Semantic Paradoxes and the Paradoxes of Truth". Field there discusses the following restriction of the naive truth schema:

T**) If True(p) then p.

He notes that this is rather weak, since it doesn't even imply that there are any truths at all. Hence, he says, one would presumably add principles like

Non-Standard Escape Routes

I've been busy working on the logic book, playing with music software, meeting friends, lazing around, looking after Magdalena (who was ill again), protesting against the war, and thinking that it was a good idea to have voted for Livingstone (as I did when I lived in London). I hope to get back to philosophy soon.

Teaching Predicate Logic

I'm thinking about how to introduce the semantics of predicate logic to beginning philosophy students. In particular, I'm interested in the interpretation of predicates and quantifiers. Last year in logic class, it seemed that most students were rather unhappy with the formal recursion on truth we were teaching them.

So I've just picked 15 random logic textbooks to see how they are doing it.


Group 1 (functions and sets): Interpretations are introduced as entities that assign to each n-ary predicate symbol a class of n-tuples of elements of the domain. (Machover, Beckermann, Bostock, Newton-Smith, Mendelson, Kutschera, Allen/Hand, Bühler)

Creation by Definition

Hereby I stipulate that "fb13" is to denote the first human born in the 13th century. Hence it might seems that "fb13 was born in the 13th century" is analytically true, true by definition. But if analytic truths are closed under logical implication, "somebody was born in the 13th century" would also be analytically true. Which it is not.

I don't think tinkering with closure under logical implication will help. Hereby I stipulate that "fb23" is to denote the first human born in the 23rd century. However, if recent progress in civilization continues, there might well be no humans in the 23rd century. And if no humans are born in the 23rd century, "fb23 is a human born in the 23rd century" is false. So it cannot be true by definition.

Even More Thoughts about Thoughts

In my last posting, I argued that to escape the cardinality problem for thoughts Frege perhaps has to give up

1) For any things there is at least one concept under which all and only those things fall.

Now (1) is clearly false if, as I think, all there is are objects -- that is, if it makes sense to quantify over absolutely everything. But if not, as Frege thinks, denying (1) is not an option. A concept is a function from things to truth values. Given that functions are not themselves things, how could there fail to be such functions?

Too Many Thoughts

A while ago, I was discussing Adam Rieger's alleged paradox in Frege's ontology (here, here, and here). I'm still confident that the Russellian version of the paradox can be blocked. But on second thought, the cardinality version of the paradox appears to be much more difficult. Here it is again.

1) For any things there is at least one concept under which all and only those things fall.

2) For each of these concepts, there exists the thought that Ben Lomond falls under it.

3) All these thoughts are different.

4) All thoughts are objects.

From (1)-(3) it follows that there are more thoughts than objects (2^k if k is the number of objects), contradicting (4).

Silly Question

Ulrich Blau is professor of logic in Munich. For the last 30 years or so he's been working on an enormous book in which he solves all known and several unknown problems in logic, foundations of mathematics, and philosophy in general. If you ever come across that book (it's not published yet), I'd strongly recommend you just skip the non-technical introduction (and conclusion). It's really getting much better where the formulas begin. Anyway, in the introductory chapter I found a silly question that I once discovered myself when I still went to school:

Does this question have an answer?

(In Blau's version, it goes "Can you answer the question you are now reading either affirmatively or negatively?")

< 79 older entriesHome702 newer entries >