< 121 older entriesHome654 newer entries >

Implicit Definitions, Part 4: Summing Up (And a Partial Defence of Implicit Definition)

In the previous three entries, I've tried to argue that there are no genuinely implicit definitions: Whenever a new expression is introduced via an alleged implicit definition, either there is no question of definition at all, as in the case of new expressions used as bound variables in mathematics, or there is an explicit definition nearby.

This latter fact, that sometimes explicit definitions are only nearby, provides a partial vindication of implicit definitions. For example, let's assume that folk psychology implicitly defines "pain". But folk psychology itself is not equivalent to the nearby explicit definition. To get an explicit definition, we have to turn folk psychology into something like its Carnap sentence. So the theory itself could be called a genuinely implicit definition.

Implicit Definitions, Part 3: Contextual Definition

I've said that an explicit definition introduces a new expression by stipulating that it be semantically equivalent to an old expression. If there are no non-explicit definitions, this means that you can only define expressions that are in principle redundant. Aren't there counterexamples to this claim?

Consider the definition of the propositional connectives. We can explicitly define some of them with the help of others, but what if we want to define all of them from scratch? The common strategy here is to recursively provide necessary and sufficient conditions for the truth of a sentence governed by the connective: A wedge B is true iff A is true and B is true.

Implicit Definitions, Part 2: Theoretical Terms

Scientific theories are often said to implicitly define their theoretical terms: phlogiston theory implicitly defines "phlogiston", quantum mechanics implicitly defines "spin". This is easily extended to non-scientific theories: ectoplasm theory implicitly defines "ectoplasm", folk psychology implicitly defines "pain".

The first problem from the mathematical case applies here too: Since all these theories make substantial claims about reality, their truth is not a matter of stipulation. For example, no stipulation can make phlogiston theory true. That's why, according to the standard Ramsey-Carnap-Lewis account, what defines a term (or several terms) t occurring in a theory T(t) is not really the stipulation of T(t) itself, but rather the stipulation of something like its 'Carnap sentence' existsx T(x) to T(t). All substantial claims in T(t) are here cancelled out by the antecedent.

Implicit Definitions, part 1: Mathematics

I vaguely believe that there are no implicit definitions. So I've decided to write a couple of entries to defend this belief. The defence may well lead me to give it up, though. Anyway, here is part 1.

Explicit definitions introduce a new expression by stipulating that it be in some sense synonymous or semantically equivalent to an old expression. For ordinary purposes this can be done without the use of semantic vocabulary by stipulations of the form

Luxury Flat

This weekend, I've moved into my new flat, which has both a bath room and a fridge, and also lot's of funny records from the 1970s.

How Many Sciences is Semantics?

I often wonder to what extent different theories and approaches in philosophy of language are conflicting theories about the same matter, or rather different theories about different matters. For example, some theories try to describe the cognitive processes involved in human speaking and understanding; Others try to find systematic rules for how semantic properties (like truth value or truth conditions) of complex expressions are determined by semantic properties (like reference or intension) of their components; Others try to spell out what mental and behavioural conditions somebody must meet in order to understand an expression (or a language); Others try to find physical relations that hold between expression tokens and other things iff these other things are in some intuitive sense the semantic values of the expression tokens; Others try to discover social rules that govern linguistic behaviour; and so on. How are all these projects related to each other?

What does the Wason Selection Task test?

I'm doing a visual memory test. On the table in front of me are twelve green and fourteen red apples, and an empty basket. The lights go out, and the instructor says to me:

"Put all the green apples into the basket". (1)

I try to do what he says. When the lights go on, you, the instructor's assistant, are given a form on which you are to tick whether I've correctly or incorrectly fulfilled the task. You see twelve green and two red apples in the basket. What do you tick?

First Thoughts About Hilbert

Today I've been reading Hilbert. I must admit that I don't really understand his view on the foundations of mathematics. It seems to me that he always confuses truth with consistency. For example, he writes in his "New Grounding":

If we can produce [a consistency proof of formalised mathematics], then we can say that mathematical statements are in fact incontestable and ultimate truths.

Obviously, Hilbert uses "true" in a very unusual way here: Both ZFC + the Continuum Hypothesis and ZFC + its negation are consistent. Hence, on Hilberts account, both CH and its negation are "incontestable and ultimate truths".

An Impossible Question

A while ago, I asked: "Could Frege's ontology be a Henkin model?". I now believe that this question doesn't make sense: A standard model of second-order logic is a (standard) Henkin model. I should have asked: "Could Frege's ontology be a non-standard Henkin model?". Even this question is, uh, questionable, because the late Frege would have certainly rejected both a standard and a Henkin semantics, as both of these employ singular terms to denote the semantic values of function expressions. So I should rather have asked: "Are Frege's logical and semantical theses satisfiable in a non-standard Henkin model?" But now, I guess, the answer is trivially Yes, because nothing you can say in higher-order logic rules out a non-standard Henkin interpretation. However, my question was not meant to be trivial. I wanted to know whether Frege is comitted to there being more concepts (values of second-order quantifiers) than objects (values of first-order quantifiers), a claim that is true in standard models, but not in some non-standard models of any (really?)* second-order theory. Unfortunately, this question can't even be asked without violating Frege's semantical theses. As he himself notes in a letter to Russell:

Are Fundamental Properties Intrinsic?

This is a problem that cropped up several times in my thesis on Lewis, but which I never seriously discussed.

Lewis argues, or rather, stipulates, that all fundamental ("perfectly natural") properties are intrinsic. I agree that fundamental extrinsic properties would be strange. For if a thing x's being F depends on the existence and the properties of other things, it seems that F-hood should be reducible to intrinsic properties (and relations) of all the things involved. Moreover, fundamental properties are supposed to be the basis for intrinsic similarity between things, and they could hardly be if they were themselves extrinsic.

< 121 older entriesHome654 newer entries >