< 209 older entriesHome566 newer entries >

Haecceitism, Materialism, Zombies, and Counterparts

If haecceitism is true, materialism is false. For if haecceitism is true, there is a world w just like ours except that you and I have traded places. By that I don't mean that in w someone with my origin or my DNA or my soul leads a life quite like yours. No, haecceitism holds that it is possible for us to trade places completely, so that in w not only my life is just like your actual life, but also my origin, DNA and soul are just like your actual origin, DNA and soul. w and our world do not differ in any qualitative respect at all. They differ only in facts that essentially involve you or me, such as the fact that in w it's you who is writing this posting. Whatever 'physical' means, it is clear that the physical facts are not of this kind. That's why materialism is false if haecceitism is true: Materialism demands that there is no difference at all between our world and any minimal physical duplicate of it.

Extreme Haecceitism

Geoff at Too Much Text points out that the implausible hyper-essentialism implied by Kripke's account of rigidity can be avoided by adopting radical anti-essentialism, the view that there are no non-trivial (qualitative) essential properties at all. On this view, even though there is a precise boundary between a thing's essential and non-essential properties, the boundary is not very mysterious because it classifies virtually all properties as non-essential.

Two Kinds of Rigidity

I want to write something about rigidity in the philosophy of mind. But first I have to say more about rigidity. (Apologies in advance: this is all going to be rather basic. But I'll need it, and I found that many people disagree with it.)

Recently I argued that the assumption that ordinary proper names are rigid designators leads to an implausibly excessive form of essentialism. But I don't want to deny the useful distinction between rigid and non-rigid designators. That is, in a sense I do believe in rigid designators. But they are not quite what rigid designators are usually supposed to be.

Extended Atoms

In my last post, I said that I do not believe that every extended thing must have parts. Sam disgrees, arguing that whenever something is extended over length h, we can restrict our attention to a part of it with length h/n for any n < h.

I do agree that all ordinary extended things have parts. And I do agree that extended things without parts are really very strange. I'm just not sure that they are impossible.

Temporal Parts and Restrictions on Fusions

There are lots of distinctions between perdurantism and endurantism (or better, between different perdurantisms and endurantisms). Here I want to talk about the following perdurantist claim:

1) Some things (that are not events) have temporal parts.

This does not imply that ordinary things like buildings and persons have temporal parts. And even if one believes the latter, it is still perfectly coherent to reject any account of intrinsic change in terms of temporal parts, or reject an account of personal identity in terms of (properties of) temporal parts, or reject an account of persistence in terms of temporal parts, or reject whatever else temporal parts are used to account for. It is also okay to accept only some of these accounts and reject others. (I for example am a perdurantist who rejects the account of persistence in terms of temporal parts: not only can I say what it is to persist through time without mentioning temporal parts, I even believe that it is possible for a thing to exist through time without having temporal parts.) That's how we get so many perdurantisms and endurantisms. (I think it would be very helpful if people discussing this matter exactly said what they say on each of these issues rather than vaguely asserting that, e.g., things are 'wholly present at different times'.)

Abstract and Concrete

What do types, sets, universals, increases, theorems, species and governments have in common that distinguishes them from sticks, stones, mountains, molecules and cities? It's not that only the latter are causally efficacious: on many accounts (e.g. those of Lewis and Kim), events -- the paradigm examples of causal efficacy -- are sets; and why shouldn't one say that if a thing's being charged produces an effect, Charge (the universal) is just as much responsible for this as the thing itself? It's also not that only the latter are located in space or time: impure sets, species, Aristotelian universals and governments arguably are spatiotemporally located as well. And by the Helen Cartwright Theorem Theorem, theorems are sometimes written on blackboards. Indeed, I'm not sure whether anything at all clearly fails to be located in time, unless we require that something located in time must undergo intrinsic change or have a beginning or an end, which sounds ad hoc. Without such restrictions, I can't see a reason to deny that e.g. numbers exist at every time. (Oddly, I'm less inclined to say that numbers exist everywhere. But I might get used to it.)

Unhelpful Trees

Today I wondered about the connection between

Under certain ideal conditions, something is conceivable iff it is possible

and

Something is possible iff it is conceivable under certain ideal conditions.

So I asked my tree prover whether

1)  for all y(Iy then  for all x(Px iff Cxy)) then  for all x(Px iff  for all y(Iy then Cxy))
and
2)  for all x(Px iff  for all y(Iy then Cxy)) then  for all y(Iy then  for all x(Px iff Cxy)).
The answer to the first question is "not valid (1764 nodes, 84 open branches)". For the second question I manually stopped the prover at "79623 nodes, 727 unticked, 35844 open branches, 18 constants". Clearly, these results are not very helpful.

Strike Asylum

Entering the philosophy library of Humboldt University got rather unpleasant two weeks ago when a couple of students decided to occupy the building as a kind of protest against planned cuts and tuition fees and capitalism and whatever. I partly support their aims (though I think cuts in the philosophy department would be quite appropriate, given its quality, and I certainly don't want any more 'democratization' of the university), but I don't see how occupying the buildings and keeping me away from doing philosophy is a good way to achieve these aims. Anyway, I'm now in Bielefeld where there are no strikes. I'll probably return to Berlin on Saturday.

Modal Epistemology

Brute necessity is hard to accept, much harder than brute possibility. If someone claims that necessarily there are no purple cows, I expect an explanation. Perhaps he knows what kind of DNA is essential for cowhood and also that this kind of DNA can never produce purple beings, and he also believes that the laws of nature are necessary. This would make his claim understandable. But suppose he had no such explanation. Suppose in fact that we all know that only a minor mutation would be required to produce purple cows, a mutation perfectly compossible with the laws of nature. And still he claims that there could not be any purple cows. This would seem bizarre.

Rigidity and Hyper-Essentialism

According to the epistemic account of vagueness, there aren't really any vague statements: When we're uncertain whether to call somebody bald that's not because he is a borderline case of baldness. There are no borderline cases. The border between being bald and not being bald is perfectly precise. It's only that we don't quite know were it runs.

Not many people believe in this account. That's surprising, because many people do believe that there are rigid designators -- terms denoting the same thing in every possible world --, and this seems to imply something that looks to me just like (an application of) the epistemic account of vagueness.

< 209 older entriesHome566 newer entries >