< 568 older entriesHome214 newer entries >

Models of laws

In The Metaphysics within Physics, Tim Maudlin raises a puzzling objection to Humean accounts of laws. (Possibly the same objection is raised by John Halpin in several earlier papers such as "Scientific law: A perspectival account".)

Scientists often consider very different models of putative laws. Such models can be understood as miniature worlds or scenarios in which the relevant laws obtain. On Humean accounts, the laws at a world are determined by the occurrent events at that world. The problem is that rival systems of laws often have models with the very same occurrent events. Whether this is a problem depends on what we mean by "the relevant laws obtain". Maudlin:

On the cardinality of worlds

For every way things might have been there is a possible world where they are that way. What does that tell us about the number of worlds?

If we identify ways things might have been ("propositions") with sentences of a particular language, or with semantic values of such sentences, the answer will depend on the language and will generally be small (countable). But that's not what I have in mind. It might have been that a dart is thrown at a spatially continuous dartboard, and each point on the board is a location where the dart's centre might have landed. These are continuum many possibilities, although they cannot be expressed, one by one, in English.

Humean Everettian chances

Many of our best scientific theories make only probabilistic predications. How can such theories be confirmed or disconfirmed by empirical tests?

The answer depends on how we interpret the probabilistic predictions. If a theory T says 'P(A)=x', and we interpret this as meaning that Heidi Klum is disposed to bet on A at odds x : 1-x, then the best way to test T is by offering bets to Heidi Klum.

Nobody thinks this is the right interpretation of probabilistic statements in physical theories. Some hold that these statements are rather statements about a fundamental physical quantity called chance. Unlike other quantities such as volume, mass or charge, chance pertains not to physical systems, but to pairs of a time and a proposition (or perhaps to pairs of two propositions, or to triples of a physical system and two propositions). The chance quantity is independent of other quantities. So if T says that in a certain type of experiment there's a 90 percent probability of finding a particle in such-and-such region, then T entails nothing at all about particle positions. Instead it says that whenever the experiment is carried out, then some entirely different quantity has value 0.9 for a certain proposition. In general, on this interpretation our best theories say nothing about the dynamics of physical systems. They only make speculative claims about a hidden magnitude independent of the observable physical world.

Bader against contingent and occasional identity

In a nice little paper, "The Non-Transitivity of the Contingent and Occasional Identity Relations", Ralf Bader argues that if identity is relative to times or worlds, then it becomes non-transitive and thus no longer qualifies as real identity.

Following Gallois, Bader assumes that a proponent of occasional identity must insist that identity statements are always relativised to a time. Now he considers a case where between times t1 and t2, two objects B and D simultaneously undergo fission in such a way that one fission product of B fuses with one fission product of D. Of the three resulting objects A, C and E, one (C) is a fission product of both B and D. Bader argues that at the initial time t1, it is then true that A=C and C=E, but not that A=E. So identity at t1 is not transitive.

Gallois on occasional identity

In the (Northern) summer, I wrote a short survey article on contingent identity. The word limit did not allow me to go into many details. In particular, I ended up with only a brief paragraph on Andre Gallois's theory of occasional identity, although I would have liked to say a lot more. So here are some further thoughts and comments on Gallois's account.

In his 1998 monograph Occasions of Identity, Gallois defends the view that things can be identical at some times and worlds and non-identical at others. For simplicity, I'll focus only on the temporal dimension here. Gallois begins with a long list of scenarios where it is intuitive to say that things are identical at one time but not at others. For example, when an amoeba A fissions into two amoebae B and C, it is tempting to say that B and C were identical prior to the fission and non-identical afterwards.

Representation theorems and the indeterminacy of mental content

To what extent are the beliefs and desires of rational agents determined by their actual and counterfactual choices? More precisely, suppose we are given a preference order that obtains between a possible act A and a possible act B iff the relevant agent is disposed to choose A over B. Say that a pair (C,V) of a credence function C and a utility (desirability) function V fits the preference order iff, whenever A is preferred over B, then A has higher expected utility than B by the lights of (C,V). Now, to what extent does a rational preference order constrain fitting credence-utility pairs?

Paper jam

Some recent papers:

Counterexamples to Stalnaker's Thesis

I like a broadly Kratzerian account of conditionals. On this account, the function of if-clauses is to restrict the space of possibilities on which the rest of the sentence is evaluated. For example, in a sentence of the form 'the probability that if A then B is x', the if-clause restricts the space of possibilities to those where A is true; the probability of B relative to this restricted space is x iff the unrestricted conditional probability of B given A is x. This account therefore valides something that sounds exactly like "Stalnaker's Thesis" for indicative conditionals:

Possible worlds and non-principal ultrafilters

It is natural to think of a possible world as something like an extremely specific story or theory. Unlike an ordinary story or theory, a possible world leaves no question open. If we identify a theory with a set of propositions, a possible world could be defined as a theory T which is

  1. maximally specific: T contains either P or ~P, for every proposition P;
  2. consistent: T does not contain P and ~P, for any proposition P;
  3. closed under conjunction and logical consequence: if T contains both P and Q, then it contains their conjunction P & Q, and if T contains P, and P entails Q, then T contains Q.

It is often useful to go in the other direction and identify propositions with sets of possible worlds. We can then analyse entailment as the subset relation, negation as complement and conjunction as intersection. Of course, we may not want to say that a world is a (non-empty) set of (consistent) propositions and also that a consistent proposition is a non-empty set of worlds, since these sets should eventually bottom out. But that doesn't seem very problematic, and it is easily fixed as long as there is a simple 1-1 correspondence between worlds and logically closed, consistent and maximally specific theories. In particular, one might suspect that on the present definitions, every logically closed, consistent and maximally specific theory uniquely corresponds to a possible world, namely the sole member of the intersection of the theory's members.

Poor one-boxers

Imagine you're a hedonist who doesn't care about other people, nor about your past or your distant future. All you care about is how much money you can spend today. Fortunately, you're on a pension that pays either $100 or $1000 every day, plus an optional bonus. How much you get is determined as follows. Every morning, a psychologist shows up to study your brain. Then he puts two boxes in front of you, one opaque, the other transparent. You can choose to take either both boxes or only the opaque one. The transparent box contains a $10 bill. The opaque box contains nothing if the psychologist has predicted that you will take both boxes; if he has predicted that you will take one box, it contains $100. The psychologist's predictions are about 99% accurate. The content of your boxes is your bonus payment. In addition, you get your ordinary payment, which is either $100 or $1000 depending on how many boxes you took the previous day: if you took both, you now get $1000, otherwise $100. The ordinary payment is given to you before the psychologist studies your brain, so by the time you choose between the two boxes, you already know how much you received. What do you do?

< 568 older entriesHome214 newer entries >