< 630 older entriesHome151 newer entries >

Necessitarianism, dispositionalism, and dynamical laws

Necessitarian and dispositionalist accounts of laws of nature have a well-known problem with "global" laws like the conservation of energy, for these laws don't seem to arise from the dispositions of individual objects, nor from necessary connections between fundamental properties. It is less well-known that a similar, and arguably more serious, problem arises for dynamical laws in general, including Newton's second law, the Schrödinger equation, and any other law that allows one to predict the future from the present.

Is it ever rational to calculate expected utilities?

Decision theory says that faced with a number of options, one should choose an option that maximizes expected utility. It does not say that before making one's choice, one should calculate and compare the expected utility of each option. In fact, if calculations are costly, decision theory seems to say that one should never calculate expected utilities.

Informally, the argument goes as follows. Suppose an agent faces a choice between a number of straight options (going left, going right, taking an umbrella, etc.), as well as the option of calculating the expected utility of all straight options and then executing whichever straight option was found to have greatest expected utility. Now this option (whichever it is) could also be taken directly. And if calculations are costly, taking the option directly has greater expected utility than taking it as a result of the calculation.

New server

I've moved all my websites to a new server. Let me know if you notice anything that stopped working. (Philosophy blogging will resume shortly as well.)

Overlapping acts

I'm currently teaching a course on decision theory. Today we discussed chapter 2 of Jim Joyce's Foundations of Causal Decision Theory, which is excellent. But there's one part I don't really get.

Joyce mentions that Savage identifies acts with functions from states to outcomes, and that Jeffrey once suggested representing such functions as conjunctions of material conditionals: for example, if an act maps S1 to O1 and S2 to O2, the corresponding proposition would be (S1 → O1) & (S2 → O2). According to Joyce, this conception of acts "cannot be correct" (p.62). That's the part I don't really get.

Philosophical models and ordinary language

A lot of what I do in philosophy is develop models: models of rational choice, of belief update, of semantics, of communication, etc. Such models are supposed to shed light on real-world phenomena, but the connection between model and reality is not completely straightforward.

For example, consider decision theory as a descriptive model of real people's choices. It may seem straightforward what this model predicts and therefore how it can be tested: it predicts that people always maximize expected utility. But what are the probabilities and utilities that define expected utility? It is no part of standard decision theory that an agent's probabilities and utilities conform in a certain way to their publicly stated goals and opinions. Assuming such a link is one way of connecting the decision-theoretic model with real agents and their choices, but it is not the only (and in my view not the most fruitful) way. A similar question arises for the agent's options. Decision theory simply assumes that a range of "acts" are available to the agent. But what should count as an act in a real-world situation: a type of overt behaviour, or a type of intention? And what makes an act available? Decision theory doesn't answer these questions.

Beliefs, degrees of belief, and earthquakes

There has been a lively debate in recent years about the relationship between graded belief and ungraded belief. The debate presupposes something we should regard with suspicion: that there is such a thing as ungraded belief.

Compare earthquakes. I'm not an expert on earthquakes, but I know that they vary in strength. How exactly to measure an earthquake's strength is to some extent a matter of convention: we could have used a non-logarithmic scale; we could have counted duration as an aspect of strength, and so on. So when we say that an earthquake has magnitude 6.4, we characterize a central aspect of an earthquake's strength by locating it on a conventional scale.

Validity judgments

Philosophers (and linguists) often appeal to judgments about the validity of general principles or arguments. For example, they judge that if C entails D, then 'if A then C' entails 'if A then D'; that 'it is not the case that it will be that P' is equivalent to 'it will be the case that not P'; that the principles of S5 are valid for metaphysical modality; that 'there could have been some person x such that actually x sits and actually x doesn't sit' is an unsatisfiable contradiction; and so on. In my view, such judgments are almost worthless: they carry very little evidential weight.

Reduction and coordination

The following principles have something in common.

Conditional Coordination Principle.
A rational person's credence in a conditional A->B should equal the ratio of her credence in the corresponding propositions B and A&B; that is, Cr(A->B) = Cr(B/A) = Cr(B)/Cr(A&B).
Normative Coordination Principle.
On the supposition that A is what should be done, a rational agent should be motivated to do A; that is, very roughly, Des(A/Ought(A)) > 0.5.
Probability Coordination Principle.
On the supposition that the chance of A is x, a rational agent should assign credence x to A; that is, roughly, Cr(A/Ch(A)=x) = x.
Nomic Coordination Principle.
On the supposition that it is a law of nature that A, a rational agent should assign credence 1 to A; that is, Cr(A/L(A)) = 1.

All these principles claim that an agent's attitudes towards a certain kind of proposition rationally constrain their attitudes towards other propositions.

Do laws explain regularities?

Humeans about laws of nature hold that the laws are nothing over and above the history of occurrent events in the world. Many anti-Humeans, by contrast, hold that the laws somehow "produce" or "govern" the occurrent events and thus must be metaphysically prior to those events. On this picture, the regularities we find in the world are explained by underlying facts about laws. A common argument against Humeanism is that Humeans can't account for the explanatory role of laws: if laws are just regularities, then then laws can't really explain the regularities — so the charge — since nothing can explain itself.

Confirmation and singular propositions

In discussions of the raven paradox, it is generally assumed that the (relevant) information gathered from an observation of a black raven can be regimented into a statement of the form Ra & Ba ('a is a raven and a is black'). This is in line with what a lot of "anti-individualist" or "externalist" philosophers say about the information we acquire through experience: when we see a black raven, they claim, what we learn is not a descriptive or general proposition to the effect that whatever object satisfies such-and-such conditions is a black raven, but rather a "singular" proposition about a particular object -- we learn that this very object is black and a raven. It seems to me that this singularist doctrine makes it hard to account for many aspects of confirmation.

< 630 older entriesHome151 newer entries >