< 301 older entriesHome474 newer entries >

Metaphysics

Metaphysical debates about causation, consciousness, chance, change, mathematics, or modality have a lot in common. In all cases, metaphysical theories try to tells us what, if anything, makes a certain class of statements true. Among the possible answers, we usually find suggestions to reject the alleged phenomena, to declare them as primitive, and to reduce them in various ways to something else. But on closer inspection, there appear to be big differences, in particular with respect to what is required for a reduction.

Logicalism, Physicalism and David Lewis

In "Tharp's Third Theorem", Lewis agrees with Jackson that "all of us are committed to the a priori deducibility of the manifest way things are from the fundamental way things are (whatever that may be)" (TTT, p.96). His somewhat cryptic argument isn't quite the same as Jackson's though, and it seems that he avoids the mistake I mentioned yesterday.

Note that Lewis doesn't say we're committed to the a priori deducibility of all truths from the fundamental truths. Instead, he speaks of the "fundamental way things are", or from "contingent truths, supervenient on the fundamental way things are" (TTT 96). (In case that's not clear: Like Lewis, I use "truth" for "true sentence", not e.g. for "true proposition".)

More on Logicalism, Physicalism and Frank Jackson

Let logicalism ("logicism" was already taken) be the claim that all truths supervene upon purely logical truths, where a purely logical truth is a truth that contains only logical terms, including terms from second order modal logic.

Logicalism immediately follows from this purely logical truth ('[]' is the box, 'ACT' the actually operator):

p <-> []((x)(F)(Fx <-> ACT(Fx)) -> p)

While all truths therefore supervene upon the purely logical truths, not all truths are a priori deducible from the purely logical truths. For instance, that water covers most of the earth isn't. So we have a counterexample to the claim that whenever all truths supervene on the F-truths, then all truths are a priori deducible from the F-truths.

Serious Metaphysics and A Priori Entailment

Serious Metaphysics, in Jackson's sense, tries to identify a limited set of truths (i.e. true sentences) that entail (i.e. strictly imply) all truths. So what about

*) Everything is just as it actually is?
   ((p)(p <-> actually p), or (x)(F)(Fx <-> actually Fx))

(*) is true. It entails all other truths: whenever S is true, then so is "necessarily, if (*) then S". And it is fairly simple and economic: for instance, it doesn't contain macrophysical or phenomenal terms. Still, it's not serious metaphysics. What's wrong?

Lewis on Idiosyncratic Analysis

Apropos conceptual differences, Lewis didn't seem to care much about whether his analyses exactly matched other people's semantic intuitions:

In "Veridical Halluzination and Prosthetic Vision", he claims that prosthetic vision is properly called "seeing". He continues:

If you insist that "strictly speaking", prosthetic vision isn't really seeing, then I'm prepared to concede you this much. Often we do leave semantic questions unsettled when we have no practical need to settle them. Perhaps this is such a case, and you are resolving a genuine indeterminacy in the way you prefer. But if you are within your rights, so, I insist, am I. I do not really think my favoured usage is at all idiosyncratic. But it scarcely matters: I would like to understand it whether it is idiosyncratic or not. (p.280 in Papers II)

Another example: In Convention, he suggests that a regularity to dress in a particular way doesn't count as conventional if many people conforming to the regularity want others not to conform (so that they can poke fun at them). Realizing that this classification isn't obvious he notes:

If the reader disagrees, I can only remind him that I did not undertake to analyze anyone's concept of convention but mine. (p.47)

He speaks of reminding the reader because he had already mentioned in the introduction that there might be no clear common concept of convention. But, he adds, "what I call convention is an important phenomenon under any name" (p.3).

Wissenschaftstheorie Studienführer

In case anyone's interested, here is the preliminary study guide for my Wissenschaftstheorie course (postscript file, German). I've decided to spend a little time on constructivism and relativism because there's a parallel course on sociology of science, and at least in Germany it is common sociological practice to talk as if constructivism and relativism were true. (My principle of charity demands not to take this talk literally. It usually makes sense if one substitutes "theory" for "reality" and "belief" for "truth".)

A Question about Brian Weatherson's Naturalness Constraint

On rereading Brian's counterexamples paper, I'm not so sure anymore I understand him correctly: Are the semantic values of predicates that are supposed to be fairly natural (unions of ranges of) C-intensions or (unions of ranges of) A-intensions? Philosophical analyses usually spell out A-intensions: they tell us that pain is what occupies the pain role, or that water is the watery stuff, not that pain is C-fiber firing and water H2O. So if the naturalness of semantic values speaks in favour of simple analyses, it should be naturalness of A-intensions. On the other hand, the fish example makes more sense if it is understood as talking about C-intensions (which would also match a suggestion sometimes made by Jackson, e.g. on p.95 of "From H2O to water", that we might analyse "water" as something like "the most natural kind roughly meeting such and such conditions"). The A-intension of "fish" presumably isn't all too natural, among other things it contains whales at worlds where the fishy animals of our acquaintance are mostly whales.

Experiments on Semantic Intuitions

A few more comments on why I think the setup of Weinberg, Nichols and Stich's experiments on intuitions is unfortunate. The problem seems particularly obvious in the experiments on semantic intuitions reported by Machery, Mallon, Nichols and Stich, but I think it carries over to many (though perhaps not all) of the experiments of Weinberg, Nichals and Stich. Here is one of the questions Machery, Mallon, Nichols and Stich asked:

Conceptual Differences

I don't understand what's so bad about admitting that people may use and understand the same words in slightly different ways.

Suppose there is a community of Martians who have a word for true justified belief, but no word for knowledge. When these Martians learn English, they might at first take "knowledge" to be synonymous with their word: the difference hardly shows up in ordinary contexts. So when they use "knowledge", they mean true justified belief.

Optimism

Eliezer Yudkowsky, in his Intuitive Explanation of Bayesian Reasoning, argues that it is irrational to justify the belief that if a biological war will break out it won't wipe out humanity by pointing out that one is an optimist:

p(you are currently an optimist | biological war occurs within ten years and wipes out humanity) =
p(you are currently an optimist | biological war occurs within ten years and does not wipe out humanity)

< 301 older entriesHome474 newer entries >