< 529 older entriesHome252 newer entries >

Diodorus and actuality

Let [] and <> express alethic necessity and alethic possibility, let @ stand for 'actually', and L for 'it is unalterable that'. We are going to prove that if something happens, then it is unalterable that it happens.

We need the following principles:

  1. A <-> <>@A.
    Something is the case iff it is possibly actually the case.
  2. <>A -> L<>A.
    If something is alethically possible, one cannot make it alethically impossible.
  3. L(A -> B) -> (LA -> LB).
    If A -> B and A are both unalterable, then so is B.
  4. If A is provable then LA.
    Logical truths are unalterable.

Here is the proof, with a sea battle for illustration.

The unity and disunity of epistemic values

Alvin Goldman has just been giving this year's summer school here in Cologne. When he put forward his view that what distinguishes good ways of belief formation from other ways is their truth-conduciveness, I found myself disagreeing and claiming that there is no general principle that distinguishes the good ways from others. This is somewhat surprising given that I've often claimed in recent times that the only epistemic criterion for evaluating belief-formation is truth-conduciveness. Here is how I think the two claims can go together.

Names and descriptions in modal logic

In the old days, it was common to exclude individual constants from quantified modal logic in favour of Russellian descriptions. I can see how this works if we have either fixed domains (the same individuals populating all worlds) or possibilist quantifiers. But in such systems individual constants don't cause much trouble anyway. Can one also make the description move in more liberal systems? I don't see how, but I guess I'm just missing something obvious.

Consider a formula "possibly, a is F". We want to replace the name "a" by a description "the A". Does the description get narrow scope ("possibly, the A is F") or wide scope ("the A is possibly F")? Either way, we seem to get the wrong result.

Lewis on Counterfactuals, Similarity, and Morgenbesser's Coin

There is a mistake on page 49 of Lewis's "Counterfactual dependence and time's arrow" (1979). Since the mistake seems to be repeated all the time, it might be worth pointing it out.

Page 49 is where Lewis lists similarity standards for his analysis of counterfactuals. The analysis, recall, says that "if A were the case, then C" is true iff the closest A-worlds are C-worlds (or, more precisely, iff either there are no A-worlds or some A&C-worlds are closer to the actual world than any A&~C world). Closeness is a matter of similarity, and Lewis indicates what the relevant respects of similarity might be for certain ordinary counterfactuals in section 3.3 of his 1973 book, and again in the 1979 article on counterfactual dependence. Roughly, the closest A-worlds are those that perfectly match the actual world across as much of spacetime as possible without diverse and widespread violations of the actual laws. This won't do for indeterministic worlds, where generally no laws need to be violated at all in order to ensure perfect match of futures even after earlier divergence. So Lewis restricts his standards to deterministic worlds, returning to the indeterministic case in the 1986 postscript to the 1979 paper.

Homecoming

I'm back in Germany. Nice and rainy here. Blogging will also resume at some point or other.

Content, form, and hyperintensions

I'm off to the Blue Mountains for a week. In lieu of philosophical content, here is a rant on semantic contents and hyperintensions that I wrote last year.

When philosophers talk about meanings (or contents, or semantic values), they rarely explain what these things are meant to do -- what constraints an adequate theory of meaning would have to meet. Trying to figure out those constraints from what is implicitly used in discussions and arguments, one gets a laundry list of miscellaneous features with hardly any theoretical unity. Meanings are supposed to determine (together with syntactic structure) the truth-value of sentences; they are supposed to be known by competent speakers; they are supposed to be conventionally associated with symbols and sounds; they are supposed to track what a sentence is (intuitively) about, and also in which possible worlds it is (intuitively?) true; they are supposed to be part of a model of how our brain processes and generates words; they are supposed to be possible objects of beliefs and desires; they are supposed to play various roles in speech act theory; they are supposed to the referents of 'that' clauses; they are supposed be such that one can truly utter 'Fred said that P' if and sonly if Fred uttered a sentence whose meaning is the same as the meaning of 'P'. And so on and on.

philpapers

The "something even bigger" that I mentioned when I made the online papers feed public has finally arrived: philpapers.org.

News

Sometime later this year I will move to Cologne (Germany) as part of a recently approved Emmy Noether project on apriority and understanding. The other parts of the project so far are Brendan Balcerak Jackson and Magdalena Balcerak Jackson, but we're looking for PhD students. If you might be interested, here are the details.

Unrelatedly, I made some changes to the blog. Let me know if anything's broken.

Lewis book

I forgot to mention that my book on Lewis has been released a couple of weeks ago. It's a distant descendant of my PhD thesis, and in German.

Values and consequences in economics and quantum mechanics

One of the novelties in Richard Jeffrey's "Logic of Decision" (1965) was to unify the space over which probabilities and values are defined: both probability and desirability are distributed over the space of possible worlds, of ways things might be. By contrast, in earlier theories like that of Savage, probabilities were defined over states (or events) and utilities over consequences, which were taken to be distinct kinds of things. Technically, this difference between Savage and Jeffrey isn't terribly important as long as anything an agent may care about can be found in the set of 'consequences'. However, the distinction and the labeling in Savage's treatment carries a danger to overlook the complexity of human values. This has, I believe, led to a number of serious mistakes.

< 529 older entriesHome252 newer entries >