< 555 older entriesHome226 newer entries >

Assessing the evidence differently

Alice is randomly selected from her population to be tested for a rare genetic disorder that affects about one in 10,000 people. The test is accurate 99 percent of the time, both among subjects that have the disorder and among subjects that don't. Alice's test comes back positive.

Call the information in the previous paragraph E, and suppose it's all you know about the situation. How confident are you that Alice has the disorder?

Letting our subjective probabilities be guided by the stated frequencies, we can use Bayes' Theorem to figure out that P(disorder | positive) = P(positive | disorder) * P(disorder) / (P(positive | disorder) * P(disorder) + P(positive | ~disorder) * P(~disorder)) = 0.99 * 0.0001 / (0.99 * 0.0001 + 0.01 * 0.9999) = 0.0098. Assume then that your degree of belief is about 0.01.

Conditional probabilities and Humphreys' Paradox

Expressions like 'P(A/B)', or 'the probability of A given B', seem to be used in various different ways. On one usage, P(A/B) equals P(AB)/P(B), at least if P(B) > 0. Call this the ratio usage. Simple versions of the ratio usage define P(A/B) as P(AB)/P(B), and so entail that P(A/B) is undefined whenever P(B)=0. But I would like to admit views into the family on which P(A/B) is taken as a primitive binary probability, governed by something like the Popper-Renyi conditions.

Multi-indexing and the intransparancy of truth

One might suggest that for any English sentence S, 'S is true' has the same meaning as S. Assuming compositionality, it would follow that the two are intersubstitutable in every context. But they are not.

First of all, they are not intersubstitutable in attitude reports and speech reports. I don't think this is very problematic because such reports are partly quotational, and of course expressions with the same meaning aren't always intersubstitutable inside quote marks. But 'S is true' and S are also not intersubstitutable in simple intensional contexts, as witnessed by examples like

Paradoxes for "expresses the proposition"

There are familiar semantic paradoxes for "truth" and "reference", such as the Liar paradox and Berry's paradox. I would have thought that there should be similar paradoxes for "expression", i.e. for the relation between a sentence S and the proposition expressed by S. A quick duckduckgo search didn't come up with anything. Pointers?

Here is a Liar-style one I came up with myself. Assume propositions are sets of worlds (which is the case I'm interested in). Consider the sentence

E: E expresses the empty set.

If E is true, then the proposition it expresses contains the actual world, in which case E doesn't express the empty set. So E can't be true. Since we've just proved not-E from no empirical assumptions, ~E expresses the set of all worlds. Hence E expresses the empty set. So E is true. Contradiction.

One more

Yet another paper on counterpart-theoretic semantics: Generalising Kripke Semantics for Quantified Modal Logics. This one is a bit more technical than the others. I use a broadly counterpart-theoretic model theory to construct completeness proofs for very basic quantified modal logics, such as the combination of positive free logic and K. I also play around with adding an object-language substitution operator. There are some unfinished sections at the end, but since I haven't been working on this since January, I thought I might as well upload the current version. All the proofs are spelled out in detail, which makes the whole thing ridiculously long.

I'm not much of a logician, so I'd be very interested to hear if this looks like it is worth pursuing any further.

Two papers on counterpart semantics

I've thought a bit about counterpart-theoretic semantics last year, both for natural language and for quantified modal logic. Here's a paper in which I present my preferred version of this framework as applied to natural language: Counterpart Theory and the Paradox of Occasional Identity. Apart from the semantics itself, my main claim is that the advantages of counterpart semantics do not require the metaphysics of "counterpart theory".

Here is another paper which covers related grounds, but from a more logical point of view: How Things are Elsewhere: Adventures in Counterpart Semantics. Comments on either paper are very welcome.

Online Papers Feed and Source

I've just replaced the Online Papers in Philosophy Feed by a newer version. Let me know if you run into any problems with that. (You may also consider switching to a feed from PhilPapers.)

Have I mentioned that the source code for the scripts that generate the feed is on github? Well, now I have.

(While I'm in the swing of mentioning, I might as well also mention (i) that my paper on updating self-locating beliefs is forthcoming in Phil Studies, (ii) that I won't be at the AAP this year, although I will be at various other events, like here, here and there, and (iii) that Holly and I are not "in a relationship" any more. In case you wondered about any of these.)

Coarse-grained meanings and impossible worlds

To some extent, one can account for semantic phenomena without assigning meanings to words or sentences or thoughts. For instance, we might say that beliefs and other attitudes are relations to sentences, i.e. to strings of symbols. Roughly, to believe a sentence S is to be disposed to utter (or assent to) S (or some translation of S) under certain conditions. When people talk to each other, such dispositions may be transferred: after hearing me utter the sounds "it is raining", you acquire the disposition to utter those sounds yourself. Apart from communication, we can also account for things like synonymy and analyticity. Roughly, two sentences are synonymous if necessarily, anyone who stands in the belief relation to one of them also stands in the belief relation to the other. There is no compositional semantics in this picture, because there is no semantics at all. But there might be recursive rules for translating from one language to another.

Lewis on updating and self-location

A lot has been written in the last 10 years or so on updating self-locating beliefs, mostly in the context of the Sleeping Beauty problem. One thing almost all of these papers have in common is that they quote Lewis's remark in "Attitudes de dicto and de se" (1979, p.534), where he says:

it is interesting to ask what happens to decision theory if we take all attitudes as de se. Answer: very little. We replace the space of worlds by the space of centered worlds, or by the space of all inhabitants of worlds. All else is just as before.

This is supposed to imply that Lewis took standard conditionalisation to be the correct update rule for self-locating belief.

Rational procrastination

Professor Procrastinate has to make an important phone call. The call is long overdue because Procrastinate has been playing Farmville all week. The problem is that Procrastinate values current pleasure higher than future pleasure. So when he applies his decision theory, he finds that it is better to play some more Farmville now and make the phone call later instead of making the call now: it doesn't matter much whether the call is delayed by a few more hours, and this way the immediate future will be much more pleasant.

< 555 older entriesHome226 newer entries >